The Literary Life

Home » Posts tagged '#DavidHume'

Tag Archives: #DavidHume

WHO DECIDES PROPER LITERARY TASTE

033cb39c5faddf4406052784fee8875f

Ok, so here you are, a person who loves to read and unlike so many others you know who profess to read a lot, you really like to read the classics. You can work your way through a Shakespeare play, a Henry James novel, even a David Foster Wallace novel (how about that?) with no problem. You even like great poetry. You are a certified person of taste. You deserve a sticker for your sticker book. Enjoy being smug.

Or maybe you just like to read and you’ve always wanted to know who it is that decides what literature matters and what doesn’t. In other words, who decides proper literary taste?

I would love to say I can tell you what proper literary taste is, but I have spent much of my professional life reading more cheap paperback Westerns than anybody you probably have ever known. Believe me, I know from experience: tell somebody with real taste that you read paperback Westerns and you’ll find out quick just what kind of taste people think you have.

Our friend David Hume, the Enlightenment thinker we have been looking at the last few weeks, in Of the Standard of Taste, felt he knew pretty well who it is that decides proper taste: the critics, that’s who.

Does he have a point? After all, the critics writing in The Times Literary Supplement, the New Yorker, The Paris Review, and other similar media certainly maintain powerful influence.

While Hume would not rule out our present-day very powerful critics from his treatise on standards of taste, he also would include qualified readers who have discriminating critical taste as judges of literature. Some people, he says, must be acknowledged to have better judgment than others about the aesthetic value of art, of literature.

Maybe that’s you and me. Let’s see.

So, what are the qualities required to have such taste? David Hume gives his qualifications for this discriminating critic. And he is writing about the person, not just the process of critical reading.

A proper judge of taste must have a strong sensibility, “A perfect serenity of mind, a recollection of thought, due attention to the object.” These qualities are not optional, according to Hume. Without them, “we shall be unable to judge of. . . catholic and universal beauty.” Without a strong sensibility, a person will be unable to determine the relationship “which nature has placed between the form and the sentiment will at least be more obscure; and it will require greater accuracy to trace and discern it.” If the only kind of literature you care about is cheap shoot ‘em up Westerns, you might ought to question your sensibility of discernment in literature.

“One obvious cause,” Hume says, “why many feel not the proper sentiment of beauty, is the want of that delicacy of imagination, which is requisite to convey a sensibility of those finer emotions. . . .” A delicate sentiment does not come easily and in our time with the prevailing tastes in popular culture for violence, physical and emotional, as well as anything with shock value, delicacy of sentiment rarely seems even to exist.

A proper judge of taste must be someone with great experience in literature who has plenty of opportunity to compare artworks. How can we expect any sort of measure of taste, be it ever so general or undefined, from someone whose knowledge of literature, from the greatest to the basest, is significantly limited?

Thus Hume says, “Strong sense, united to delicate sentiment, improved by practice, perfected by comparison, and cleared of all prejudice, can alone entitle critics to [this] valuable character; and the joint verdict of such, wherever they are to be found, is the true standard of taste and beauty.” A person of proper literary taste, then, must be able to clear the mind of all prejudice.”

“But where are such critics to be found?” Hume asks, and perhaps you are asking. Especially in the second decade of the 21st century?

What do you think? As I said in my last post, we have plenty of critics around us today, publishing their ideas everywhere—in books, on the web, in blogs like mine, in peer reviewed journals, everywhere. Clearly they can’t be dismissed and aren’t dismissed. What they say carries plenty of weight. But they disagree with each other at seemingly every point of discussion, right?

David Hume ends his essay on the standard of taste saying, “It is sufficient for our present purpose, if we have proved, that the taste of all individuals is not upon equal footing, and that some men in general, however difficult to be particularly pitched upon, will be acknowledged by universal sentiment to have preference above others.”

Do you agree that in fact some people do have very bad taste in literature? If so, would you not also agree that other people have better taste than those with very bad taste in literature? Do you agree that in our culture of the 21st century there is such a thing as bad taste and, at least, better taste? Whether you or I accept prevailing standards of taste, don’t they exist anyway? We can ignore them if we wish, but does that change anything ultimately?

These are the questions that matter. Not what David Hume said or thought. I used David Hume in this series on taste simply to place in front of you ideas about taste that much of our culture would find outdated but which nevertheless might still have some validity no matter how much we might deny them.

So, who decides proper literary taste today?

Write your comments in the comment box. And let’s see your comments no matter when you read this blog. None of the ideas I am approaching are time sensitive.

Let’s start a conversation. Re-blog. Re-tweet. Follow The Literary Life. The more readers who are posting comments the better.

WHAT ARE SOME BARRIERS TO ACQUIRING PROPER LITERARY TASTE?

60151824ac92c32dd25766cc65e51293

If you are a person for whom great literature matters and are clicking into The Literary Life for the first time as a result of seeing my title above on one of the social media sites, you might be a bit put off by a question about proper literary taste, or more to the point, about bad literary taste. If so, please read the other short posts on my blog from recent weeks on the idea of #Taste to have a context of a question like this.

David Hume in Of the Standard of Taste, with whom we have been working, gives several criteria for good taste, which we will look at next. But first he takes a look at improper taste and why people have it. Taste is universal, he claims, but not all people possess taste.

People who are disordered, for example: “A man in a fever would not insist on his palate as able to decide concerning flavours; nor would one, affected with the jaundice, pretend to give a verdict with regard to colours.”

Are you “disordered?” Ok, not a fair question. But do you trust your Uncle Louie who you only see at Thanksgiving to have the same proper taste as you presumably have? Or maybe ask yourself, do you know people who clearly do not have proper taste under virtually any definition of taste? Forget good taste for the moment. Is there in fact such a thing as undeniably bad taste? (Case in point, velvet paintings of Elvis.) Well, ok, then. Why?

To some degree all of us have some defects in taste: “In each creature, there is a sound and defective state; and the former alone can be supposed to afford us a true standard of taste and sentiment.” Remember that for Hume “sentiment” is the subjective element in taste whereas “judgment” is the objective and universal side.

So consider how this helps explain our own occasional bad taste even when we really have good taste.

But, probably more importantly, many of us simply do not possess what Hume would call “those finer emotions of the mind” that are “of a very tender and delicate nature.” And even when we possess such, often circumstances get in the way of our proper taste: “Those finer emotions of the mind are of a very tender and delicate nature, and require the concurrence of many favourable circumstances to make them play with facility and exactness, according to their general and established principles.”

Ok, it looks like we are not to rely upon ourselves when developing proper taste. Our sentiments might guide our preferences for this author or that. Some of us might think the Harry Potter novels are tasteful reading and others might shun anything written after 1900. These are simply our sentiments at work guiding our reading. But what about universal proper taste? Who decides for all the rest of us what matters and what doesn’t?

Well, that’s always the sticking point as we have put up in front of us from the beginning. For David Hume, only properly qualified critics have acumen enough to discover universal principles of taste.

Let’s just consider what a properly qualified critic is in the next posting. But even before we see what our representative from the eighteenth century thinks, what do you think? We have plenty of critics around us today, publishing their ideas everywhere—in books, on the web, in blogs like mine, in peer reviewed journals, everywhere. Clearly they can’t be dismissed and aren’t dismissed. What they say carries plenty of weight. But they disagree with each other at seemingly every point of discussion, right? What about the critics? Stay tuned.

Write your comments in the comment box. And let’s see your comments no matter when you read this blog. None of the ideas I am approaching are time sensitive.

Let’s start a conversation. Re-blog. Re-tweet. Follow The Literary Life. The more readers who are posting comments the better.

WHAT ELEMENTS OF LITERARY TASTE ARE UNIVERSAL?

fdb9abbe9746a8e4f8dfc4f031f88018

Let’s continue the ideas from the previous posts as we compare our 21st-century ideas of literary taste with those of the Enlightenment philosopher David Hume that represent fairly well ideas common until the latter part of the 20th century.

For Hume, as we have seen, the principles of taste are universal, and, nearly, if not entirely the same in all humanity; yet few are qualified to give judgment on any work of art, or establish their own sentiment as the standard of beauty.

Hume bases his claim for “eternal and immutable” taste upon his Enlightenment views of the universality of ideas, and he claims the standards of taste share common sources with the sciences: “Their foundation is the same with that of all the practical sciences, experience; nor are they any thing but general observations, concerning what has been universally found to please in all countries and all ages.”

For most of you today these are extraordinary claims at odds with our cultural assumptions and general democratic principles of human equality.

But Hume piles it on in Of the Standard of Taste. Of poetry specifically, he says “though poetry can never submit to exact truth, it must be confined by rules of art, discovered to the author either by genius or observation.”

Of course, even for Hume, there are exceptions to this basic standard. Obviously some poets in English literature prior to the 18th century had not always followed the rules. (Ahem, what about that most un-Enlightenment-like William Shakespeare?) Yeah, but so what, Hume concedes: “If some negligent or irregular writers have pleased,” he obviously sneers, “they have not pleased by their transgressions of rule and order, but in spite of these transgressions.” Ah, David, oh boy.

So there are exceptions to the universal elements of taste. It’s just that for all these poets who don’t follow the rules of order, “They have possessed other beauties, which are conformable to just criticism; and the force of these beauties has been able to overpower censure.”

But regardless of the exceptions, “the general rules of art are founded only upon experience and on the observation of the common sentiments of human nature.” And less we start saying that these ideas leave open to everyone having any opinion about their personal taste, Hume qualifies: “we must not imagine that, on every occasion, the feelings of men will be conformable to these rules.” But, and here’s the point to end this discussion and take up next time, BUT “few are qualified to give judgment on any work of art.” Only the few, the select, and the proud can decide what proper literary taste is.

Let’s take this idea up next time.

But do you agree or not? Write your comments in the comment box. And let’s see your comments no matter when you read this blog. None of the ideas I am approaching are time sensitive.

Let’s start a conversation. Re-blog. Re-tweet. Follow The Literary Life. The more readers who are posting comments the better.

David Hume in the News

For the several posts I have been discussing some of the ideas of the 18th-century Enlightenment thinker David Hume. Turns out he’s still popular. Check out this month’s Atlantic Monthly at http://www.theatlantic.com/magazine/archive/2015/10/how-david-hume-helped-me-solve-my-midlife-crisis/403195.

Paul Varner

1920

ARE STANDARDS FOR LITERARY TASTE IMPORTANT? WHAT ABOUT LITERARY JUDGMENT?

4ea9c73cd22bf87f281022181db263e0

Plenty of people would deny that standards for literary taste are important or even desirable. Doesn’t everybody have a right to his or her own tastes? These are important questions for anyone living the literary life and for whom serious literature matters. Who decides what is serious literature anyway?

Just for the sake of having a text to respond to for these questions I have been showing you some things David Hume, our friend from the 18th century, says in Of the Standard of Taste had to say.

I ran into Hume years ago as an undergraduate. It took me years, though, really to appreciate him (or Hume). Maybe it was because I read him in a used textbook from the college bookstore.

Anyway, Hume distinguishes between sentiment and judgment. Sentiment is what most of us think of when we refer to individual tastes. It is solely personal and therefore indisputable.

Literary judgment is something else altogether. Unlike sentiment, judgment resides outside of our selves. If I say I don’t like Steven Spielberg’s movies because I hated E.T. and all his movies were spoiled after that, I am merely expressing my personal sentiment, Hume would say.

But if I condemn outright all Steven Spielberg movies and insist they are all trash produced by an idiot, I am simply showing up myself to be the foolish one. I am displaying my poor taste. Wouldn’t just about anyone agree? Sure I can dislike Spielberg’s movies all I want. But I really cannot judge them based simply on my experience with E.T., can I? Why? Because the standard judgment of Spielberg’s movies is different from my personal sentiment?

What do you think? Use whatever terminology you like, but are there differences between personal and impersonal responses to a work of literature?

So Hume says, “It is natural for us to seek a Standard of Taste: a rule, by which the various sentiments of men may be reconciled; at least a decision, afforded, confirming one sentiment, and abandoning another.” Hmm.

Artistic beauty, then, Hume goes on to say, appeals to our common sentiments shared by all simply by reason of our being human? Do you agree? Is Hume right? Are we, by chance, human still today in postmodernity the same way Hume thinks of being human in 18th-century mid to upper class England?

While opinions might vary, Hume would continue, emotional responses are universal–to readers of sound judgment.  Alas, there’s the rub.

Not many people have sound judgment; many are uncultivated, confused, inexperienced, not sufficiently educated, or simply apathetic.

Thus, for David Hume, as I partially quoted in an earlier post, “Among a thousand different opinions which different men may entertain of the same subject, there is one, and but one, that is just and true; and the only difficulty is to fix and ascertain it.”

So there you have it; we just need to distinguish between sentiment and judgment? When I figured this out years ago it was an eye-opener, the difference between sentiment and judgment.

Is Hume right? Is there any application to how we think of literary taste today? Perhaps we can change the terminology. But is the dichotomy still relevant?

Make comments. Let’s start a conversation. Re-blog. Re-tweet. Follow The Literary Life. The more readers who are posting comments the better.

Paul Varner

 

THE GREAT VARIETY OF LITERARY TASTE

3e5ed7ede10a91cf98e07441115eb07f

This morning I am writing from my favorite coffee shop—Mezamiz Deux Coffee House. I love coffee and in my life as a scholar I heartily accepted the motto that scholars are machines for turning coffee into ideas. Now I’ve got to adapt that saying for readers as well. Oh well, let’s begin.

Why is it that great literature means so much for our lives? Of course, we could all easily tell about our favorite authors or our favorite books. But, more generally, can we isolate some of the reasons great literature, as a whole, matters so much to us?

Such questions as this, the really big questions of great literature, I want to keep exploring in A Literary Life. After all, such questions and their answers distinguish a life of literature from, say, a life of sports, or even a life of television watching.

Thus, again, matters of Taste that we are looking at recently.

We look all around us and we see an endless variety of tastes in our culture for literature and entertainment media. So much so that the most common responses to questions of taste, and of what makes something great literature anyway, are that all tastes are acceptable today and that distinctions between great literature and popular literature—or between what we once called high culture and low culture—are no longer relevant. Why do such attitudes prevail? Have they always prevailed or is our age distinct?

Our friend David Hume, the Enlightenment philosopher known for claiming, “There is no disputing of tastes,” acknowledges in Of the Standard of Taste that even in his day most people felt their individual tastes to be equal to everybody’s taste: “The great variety of Taste. . . which prevails in the world” is obvious to all.

Why is there such variety? Hume claims it is because most people “of confined knowledge” share the prejudices of their limited circle and their limited knowledge.

So what is the source of the idea that all tastes are equally valid? Is it perhaps that most people’s acquaintance with literature—good or bad—is limited?

How does this idea work? Someone you know reads widely and voraciously. He or she spends a fortune on books from Barnes & Noble. Yet their total reading experience is limited to the same kind of literature. Maybe, all they ever read are paperback westerns. Does Hume have a point? What are some implications?

He makes the contrast with “those who can enlarge their view to contemplate distant nations and remote ages” whose tastes are far broader than those who are limited.

Now, Hume does warn against arrogance and self-conceit—or in contemporary terms, against the dreaded elitism. Even the most highly educated—at least insofar as their reading is concerned—display a great variety of taste among themselves.

All this sounds pretty much like pitting the common readers against effete literary snobs. And it probably is. But, Hume says the great variety of taste among the best readers, if you will, is really not so diverse. It is “greater in reality than experience.” The vast disparity among tastes exists among those with limited experience. Not so much among those with a wide range of experience as readers.

Are these observations of David Hume from the eighteenth century still relevant for our postmodern twenty-first century? Does the great variety of taste extend to all levels of literary readership? Is it true that the tendency to claim all kinds of literary tastes equally valid comes primarily from very limited views of literature and the world around us?

Leave comments. Re-blog this post and talk about these things as you lead a literary life.

Paul Varner

 

Who Has Taste?

18d310aac1689fe146910152f53d2a3d

I was in the library of my dreams the other night, just luxuriating in the smooth floor-to-ceiling mahogany shelves with the order and symmetry of the books. There was a small desk intended for light correspondence and a green glass shade banker’s lamp. A ladder hung from the shelves and scooted along on a railing from one side to the other. This is the life, I sighed. This is heaven. I ran my fingers along the dark red wood, feeling the high polish.

Here is what a person of sophisticated taste lives like, I thought. I want to be a person of sophisticated taste. But in my hand I held an old cheap paperback Western, Max Brand’s Singing Guns, with its garish cover. Uh oh. What doesn’t belong in this sanctuary of taste?

I pushed the tacky Western aside and looked about for something concerning taste in literature. Then I remembered. I looked down the row and found what I was looking for. There they were. David Hume’s collected works.

As I start this blog on The Literary Life, I would like over the next several weeks to consider with you some of the really big questions that simply must be dealt with for anyone for whom great literature matters.

Let’s start with one of the biggest issues of all: TASTE. Particularly, of course, taste for good literature and art. So:

What is taste?

Who has taste? I mean today, in 2015?

Is there such a thing, really as taste anymore? Any distinction between good taste and bad taste?

DO YOU HAVE TASTE?

Ouch! Let’s get personal here. Do you really have good taste?!

(A bit of a disclaimer here: I’d die if anyone ever saw the playlist on my IPod. Professionally, I’ve spent quite a bit of my career as a literary scholar studying and writing about one of the lowest forms of popular literature—paperback Westerns and horrid Western movies. So, I’m not exactly in a position to be a snob when it comes to taste.)

Nevertheless, it does seem to me that the questions of taste, what it is and what’s good taste versus bad taste are pretty important for leading a literary life.